Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality by Max Tegmark (PDF)

26

 

Ebook Info

  • Published: 2014
  • Number of pages: 432 pages
  • Format: PDF
  • File Size: 13.46 MB
  • Authors: Max Tegmark

Description

Max Tegmark leads us on an astonishing journey through past, present and future, and through the physics, astronomy and mathematics that are the foundation of his work, most particularly his hypothesis that our physical reality is a mathematical structure and his theory of the ultimate multiverse. In a dazzling combination of both popular and groundbreaking science, he not only helps us grasp his often mind-boggling theories, but he also shares with us some of the often surprising triumphs and disappointments that have shaped his life as a scientist. Fascinating from first to last—this is a book that has already prompted the attention and admiration of some of the most prominent scientists and mathematicians.

User’s Reviews

Editorial Reviews: From Booklist *Starred Review* Nobel-laureate physicist Eugene Wigner regarded the power of mathematics to explain the cosmos as a baffling mystery. Tegmark offers a resolution of that mystery, arguing that mathematics describes the universe so well because the universe ultimately is mathematics. The rare intellectual daring in this claim emerges as Tegmark teases out its stunning implications not only for the visible universe but also for countless, unseen, parallel universes (on four levels!) in which all conceivable possibilities become realities. Aware of the skeptics, Tegmark demonstrates that his theorizing harmonizes with concepts now central to cosmology, particularly the astrophysical formulas for the post–Big Bang inflation that gave space its geometry. Tegmark’s mathematical paradigm also accounts for the strange fine-tuning of the universe’s fundamental constants and dispels the paradoxes surrounding quantum measurement. Lively and lucid, the narrative invites general readers into debates over computer models for brain function, over scientific explanations of consciousness, and over prospects for finding advanced life in other galaxies. Though he reflects soberly on the perils of nuclear war and of hostile artificial intelligence, Tegmark concludes with a bracingly upbeat call for scientifically minded activists who recognize a rare opportunity to make our special planet a force for cosmic progress. An exhilarating adventure for bold readers. –Bryce Christensen Review Brian Greene, physicist, author of The Elegant Universe and The Hidden Reality“Our Mathematical Universe boldly confronts one of the deepest questions at the fertile interface of physics and philosophy: why is mathematics so spectacularly successful at describing the cosmos? Through lively writing and wonderfully accessible explanations, Max Tegmark—one of the world’s leading theoretical physicists—guides the reader to a possible answer, and reveals how, if it’s right, our understanding of reality itself would be radically altered.”Michio Kaku, author of Physics of the Future “Daring, Radical. Innovative. A game changer. If Dr. Tegmark is correct, this represents a paradigm shift in the relationship between physics and mathematics, forcing us to rewrite our textbooks. A must read for anyone deeply concerned about our universe.” Ray Kurzweil, author of The Singularity is Near“Tegmark offers a fresh and fascinating perspective on the fabric of physical reality and life itself. He helps us see ourselves in a cosmic context that highlights the grand opportunities for the future of life in our universe.” Prof. Edward Witten, physicist, Fields Medalist & Milner Laureate“Readers of varied backgrounds will enjoy this book. Almost anyone will find something to learn here, much to ponder, and perhaps something to disagree with.” Prof. Andrei Linde, physicist, Gruber & Milner Laureate for development of inflationary cosmology“This inspirational book written by a true expert presents an explosive mixture of physics, mathematics and philosophy which may alter your views on reality.”Prof. Mario Livio, astrophysicist, author of Brilliant Blunders and Is God a Mathematician? “Galileo famously said that the universe is written in the language of mathematics. Now Max Tegmark says that the universe IS mathematics. You don’t have to necessarily agree, to enjoy this fascinating journey into the nature of reality.”Prof. Julian Barbour, physicist, author of The End of Time“Scientists and lay aficionados alike will find Tegmark’s book packed with information and very thought provoking. You may recoil from his thesis, but nearly every page will make you wish you could debate the issues face-to-face with him.”Prof. Seth Lloyd, Professor of quantum mechanical engineering, MIT, author of Programming the Universe“In Our Mathematical Universe, renowned cosmologist Max Tegmark takes us on a whirlwind tour of the universe, past, present—and other. With lucid language and clear examples, Tegmark provides us with the master measure of not only of our cosmos, but of all possible universes. The universe may be lonely, but it is not alone.”Prof. David Deutsch, physicist, Dirac Laureate for pioneering quantum computing“A lucid, engaging account of the various many-universes theories of fundamental physics that are currently being considered, from the multiverse of quantum theory to Tegmark’s own grand vision.”Amir Alexander, The New York Times“This is science writing at its best — dynamic, dramatic and accessible. […] ‘Our Mathematical Universe’ is nothing if not impressive. Brilliantly argued and beautifully written, it is never less than thought-provoking about the greatest mysteries of our existence.”Publishers Weekly (starred review)“Tegmark offers a fascinating exploration of multiverse theories, each one offering new ways to explain ‘quantum weirdness’ and other mysteries that have plagued physicists, culminating in the idea that our physical world is ‘a giant mathematical object’ shaped by geometry and symmetry. Tegmark’s writing is lucid, enthusiastic, and outright entertaining, a thoroughly accessible discussion leavened with anecdotes and the pure joy of a scientist at work.” Bryce Cristensen, Booklist (starred review)“Lively and lucid, the narrative invites general readers into debates over computer models for brain function, over scientific explanations of consciousness, and over prospects for finding advanced life in other galaxies. Though he reflects soberly on the perils of nuclear war and of hostile artificial intelligence, Tegmark concludes with a bracingly upbeat call for scientifically minded activists who recognize a rare opportunity to make our special planet a force for cosmic progress. An exhilarating adventure for bold readers.” Robert Matthews, BBC Focus magazine “Max Tegmark is a professor of physics at MIT and a leading expert on theories of the Universe. But he’s also arguably the nearest we have to a successor to Richard Feynman, the bongo-playing, wise-cracking physicist who proved it is possible to be smart, savvy and subversive at the same time. […] now `Mad Max’ has been given the freedom of an entire book. And he hasn’t wasted it. Around half of it is a lucid tour d’horizon of what we know about the Universe. The rest is an exhilarating expedition far beyond conventional thinking, in search of the true meaning of reality. Don’t be fooled: Tegmark is a very smart physicist, not a hand-waving philosopher, so the going gets tough in parts. But his insights and conclusions are staggering—and perhaps even crazy enough to be true.”Andrew Liddle, Nature “Cosmologist Max Tegmark has written an engaging and accessible book, Our Mathematical Universe, that grapples with this multiverse scenario. He aims initially at the scientifically literate public, but seeks to take us to—and, indeed, beyond—the frontiers of accepted knowledge. […] This is a valuable book, written in a deceptively simple style but not afraid to make significant demands on its readers, especially once the multiverse level gets turned up to four. It is impressive how far Tegmark can carry you until, like a cartoon character running off a cliff, you wonder whether there is anything holding you up.”Peter Woit, The Wall Street Journal “Our Mathematical Universe is a fascinating and well-executed dramatic argument from a talented expositor.”Edward Frenkel, The New York Times Sunday Book Review”An informative survey of exciting recent developments in astrophysics and quantum theory […] Tegmark participated in some of these pioneering developments, and he enlivens his story with personal anecdotes. […] Tegmark does an excellent job explaining this and other puzzles in a way accessible to nonspecialists. Packed with clever metaphors”Nathan Gelgud, Biographile Nathan Gelgud, Biographile “Just a few years ago, the idea of multiple universes was seen as a crackpot idea, not even on the margins of respectability. […] But now, thanks in large part to Tegmark and his pursuit of controversial ideas, the concept of multiple universes (or a multiverse) is considered likely by many experts in the field.[…] Tegmark’s clear, engaging prose style can take you down these exciting and unexpected pathways of thought without making you feel lost. […] in Our Mathematical Universe, we meet a revolutionary cosmology physicist who is hell bent on figuring out if that theory is true, how to prove it, how to use it, and what it means for the world as we know it.”Clive Cookson, Financial Times“Today multiple universes are scientifically respectable, thanks to the work of Tegmark as much as anyone. […] Physics could do with more characters like Tegmark. He combines an imaginative intellect and a charismatic presence with a determination to promote his subject […] enough will be comprehensible for non-scientific readers to enjoy an amazing ride through the rich landscape of contemporary cosmology. There are many interesting diversions from the main argument, from an assessment of threats to human civilisation (such as a 30 per cent risk of nuclear war) to the chance of intelligent life elsewhere in our galaxy (lower than astrobiologists like to think). Written in a lively and slightly quirky style, it should engage any reader interested in the infinite variety of nature.” Mark Buchanan, New Scientist “The book is an excellent guide to recent developments in quantum cosmology and the ongoing debate over theories of parallel universes….Perhaps this book is proof that the two personalities needed for science—the speculative and sceptic—can readily exist in one individual.”Peter Forbes, The Independent “In Our Mathematical Universe, Max Tegmark—a distinguished cosmologist—gives a lucid rundown of the current state of knowledge on the origin, present state, and fate of the universe(s). […] It is immensely illuminating on the reach of current cosmological theories. […] From time to time, Tegmark engagingly admits that such ideas sound like nonsense, but he makes the crucial point that if a theory makes good predictions you have to follow all of the consequences. […] His concluding chapter on the risks humanity faces is wise and bracing: he believes we “are alone in our Universe” but are capable of tackling terrible threats from cosmic accidents, or self-induced nuclear or climatic catastrophes. He doesn’t cite poets but his philosophy adds up to an updated 21st-century version of Thomas Hardy’s ‘If way to the better there be, it exacts a full look at the worst.'” Giles Whittell, The Times”mind-bending book about the cosmos” […] “Tegmark’s achievement is to explain what on earth he is talking about in language any reasonably attentive reader will understand. He is a professor at MIT, and clearly a fine teacher as well as thinker. He tackles the big, interrelated questions of cosmology and subatomic physics much more intelligibly than, say, Stephen Hawking.” Brian Rotman, The Guardian”Max Tegmark’s doorstopper of a book takes aim at three great puzzles: how large is reality? What is everything made of? Why is our universe the way it is? Tegmark, a professor of physics at MIT, writes at the cutting edge of cosmology and quantum theory in friendly and relaxed prose, full of entertaining anecdotes and down-to-earth analogies.”Stephen Hirtle, The Pittsburg Post-Gazette “Our Mathematical Universe is a delightful book in which the Swedish-born author, now at MIT, takes readers on a roller coaster ride through cosmology, quantum mechanics, parallel universes, sub-atomic particles and the future of humanity. It is quite an adventure with many time-outs along the way…. Our Mathematical Universe gives keen insight into someone who asks questions for the pure joy of answering them.” About the Author Max Tegmark is author or coauthor of more than two hundred technical papers, twelve of which have been cited more than five hundred times. He holds a Ph.D. from the University of California, Berkeley, and is a physics professor at MIT. Read more

Reviews from Amazon users which were colected at the time this book was published on the website:

⭐This review is an attempt to summarize and understand Tegmark’s two grand theories, meant to solve the two great conundrums of reality: 1. First-Origin conundrum — Why does any reality exist at all? and 2. Uniqueness conundrum — Why does our particular type of reality exist (and not some other)?Therefore, this review is mainly for those who have already read his book and are trying to decide whether or not his ideas are true (or even make sense).After first treating the reader to a history of cosmology, inflation, and quantum physics (along with a wide variety of resulting multiverses), Tegmark arrives at his two grand theories.The first is the Postal Code theory of the fundamental constants of our universe. According to Tegmark, there are 32 fundamental constants, with very precise values. If these values were slightly different, our universe would not have been stable enough to support life.Tegmark informs us that, when the planets were first discovered, scientists tried to explain why they had the particular properties (sizes, distances from the sun) that they have. However, as more star systems were discovered, scientists realized that there is no deep explanation needed for our planets’ size or orbits; other than the fact that we are located where we are; that is, a Postal Code that locates our particular planetary system within our particular galaxy.Tegmark applies this Postal Code theory to explain the Uniqueness conundrum (actually, to explain away the need to explain it). Just as our planetary system is one of a great many, if multiverse theories are correct, then our universe is just one of a (possibly infinite) number of universes.Recall that a level-I multiverse consists an infinite ‘sea’ of universes, all with the same laws of physics, but with a different set of fundamental constants. Most of these would be inhospitable for life. However, according to the Anthropic Principle (first coined by the theoretical astrophysicist Brandon Carter), we necessarily find ourselves in a universe with fundamental constants set to just the right values to support life (because, if not, we wouldn’t now be around to wonder why these constants have the values that they have).Recall that a level-II multiverse is also an infinite ‘sea’ of universes, but each with a different set of physical laws. A level-III multiverse is an infinitely branching set of alternative futures (and pasts) with each caused by the probabilistically distinct outcomes of the Schrödinger’s wave equation. When a given quantum outcome is observed, the multiverse level-III answer to why that particular outcome (and not some other) is: “All the other outcomes actually did occur, but in different level-III alternative universes.”These 3 different levels of multiverses are compatible with each other since all could be true at once. There could exist a sea of different laws of physics, within which each would contain a sea of different physical constants, within which each would exhibit a tangle of branching futures and pasts.If a level-I multiverse exists then there is no point in looking for an explanation for the particular values of these 32 fundamental constants. They are analogous to the sizes and orbits of our planets. In his Postal Code theory, when asked why Nature exhibits those specific, 32 fundamental values, the appropriate reply, according to Tegmark, should be to ask back: “Which universe are you referring to?” The answer to this question will be a Postal Code — one giving the location of our particular Universe, within the hierarchy of the first 3 levels of multiverses.The second grand theory in Tegmark’s book is his “Realty=Mathematics” theory. Almost all scientists believe that mathematical models can be used as descriptions of reality. Tegmark, however, claims that reality actually is mathematics and nothing but mathematics. Tegmark claims that reality exists simply because mathematical structures exist and because reality consists only of mathematical structures. As a result, each different mathematical structure brings about a different reality. A mathematical structure is any configuration of mathematical entities and relationships. Tegmark’s level-IV multiverse consists of an infinite set of different mathematical structures.Tegmark believes that, at the fundamental level of reality, there is just mathematics. Suppose you see a photon ph1 in location loc1 at time t1. Suppose at time t2, you see the photon disappear at loc1 and re-appear at a nearby location loc2. It might seem that photon ph1 has traveled from loc1 to loc2 during time interval [t1, t2]. However, since you can’t tag ph1 you can’t be sure that it’s the same photon. Nature could have simply made ph1 disappear at loc1 and then could have created a completely new photon ph2 in loc2 at time t2. There is no way to know. Since all fundamental particles are this way, they therefore behave only according to their mathematical properties. In this sense, they are not just described by mathematics, they are mathematical and only mathematical. That is, there is no property that they have that is not mathematical.I am familiar with this point of view (that what appears to be an abstraction might actually be real) because, as a computer scientist, I concluded many years ago that, if our universe were a simulation (inside some supercomputer created by an advanced alien civilization), then we, as inhabitants within that simulated universe, would not be able to prove whether or not we are simulated beings.If this simulation scenario happens to be the case, then the most fundamental unit of reality (for us, situated in our simulated universe) would be information. That is, the alien supercomputer would be manipulating bits of information which we, and our universe, would be composed of. Let us call this theory of reality: Reality = Information + Execution, or more concisely, Reality = Computation.In this case, information would be more fundamental than electrons and photons. Some physicists actually do take this position — that information is more fundamental in our universe than physics. For example, the physicist Viatko Vedral holds this point of view.In traditional computer science, however, physical matter/energy is more fundamental than information because the computer makes use of patterns of matter/energy to create information. The computer also makes use of the laws of physics to manipulate this information over time. Executing the computer with different programs then creates different simulations.A computer can simulate different realities. For example, a computer scientist can, by programming a computer, create a simulation of an virtual world (say, a 2-dimensional world) containing a population of 2-D artificial animals (which we will here term “animats”). Each animat’s behavior (both how it senses and manipulates its environment) could be controlled by, say, a network of simulated neurons.Students who take my graduate “Animats Modeling” class (in the CS dept. at UCLA) commonly build just such virtual universes. Animats can mate, produce offspring, and evolve, as the result of simulated mutations to their simulated genes.Most computer scientists believe that, if we are virtual creatures, then the alien programmer must be currently executing the program that brings our universe into being. Without execution our universe would not come into existence or exhibit its dynamics.For Tegmark’s Reality=Mathematics theory to have a chance of being correct he needs to first eliminate the requirement that something must be executing; otherwise his theory would be identical to that of Reality=Computation.The problem with the Reality=Computation theory is that it does not solve the First-Origin conundrum. The alien programmer will not be able to execute an infinite number of universes that are postulated in multiverse theories and, more importantly, we would still be left with having to explain how the matter, energy, and physical laws of the alien’s universe came about. After all, the alien’s computer needs its own universe (with its own laws of physics) in order to execute the program that creates our universe. Thus, we are still left with a First-Origin conundrum.However, if Tegmark can eliminate the need for execution (i.e. dynamic changes in the memory of a computer over time) then he can replace Reality=Computation with Reality=Mathematics.Tegmark achieves this by pointing out that Einstein’s space-time theory views time as an illusion. Instead of time moving forward (like a river), time is statically laid out, just like another spatial dimension. In the space-time theory of reality, the past and future have equal status. They both co-exist within a single, static space-time geometry. That is, there is no special present “moment” that is moving along. Motion also does not exist (since motion is how time is measured). In his book Tegmark gives the example of the moon going around the Earth as the Earth goes around the Sun. A space-time diagram of this situation is displayed as a kind of bent slinky. All temporal dynamics have been eliminated.Why do we still experience the illusion of motion (i.e., change over time) if there is no motion of any sort? This is not explained by Tegmark. Consider a movie. We know that the motion of the characters that we see in a movie is an illusion. The movie consists of a series of static frames that are displayed in sequence as time unfolds and so the illusion is not of motion; the illusion is of SMOOTH (as opposed to jerky) character motion. The explanation is that our brains create representations that transform the jerky motion into smooth, continuous character motion. If, however, the frames were never displayed over time (rather, all laid out statically, within a space-time coordinate system), then it would be difficult to explain why we experience the movie as unfolding (because neither we nor the projector would be moving). (It must be difficult to explain the illusion of motion — given a space-time view of the universe — because I have not yet come upon a reasonable explanation for this illusion in my readings on space-time theory.)But let us leave this problem aside and accept Tegmark’s premise: namely, that motion (and therefore time also) is an illusion. Thus, the execution of some computer (to create a virtual reality) is no longer required. All that is required now is the mathematical structure of space-time itself!Where does this space-time structure come from? Well, it comes from mathematics, which supplies such structures. Tegmark now applies his Postal Code strategy: He states that all possible mathematical structures exist within a level-IV multiverse of mathematical structures. Since we exist, we must exist within one of these structures. Using the Anthropic Principle, we must exist within a mathematical reality that is structured coherently enough to support life.Tegmark argues that mathematical structures exist independent of our awareness of them. For example, if we place 2 things next to 3 other things, we will get 5 things (whether or not we are there to notice). Since mathematical structures exist independent of our minds and since reality is fundamentally mathematical, voila!, reality comes into being simply because mathematical structures have their own independent existence!Tegmark’s solution to the First-Origin conundrum can now be summarized as: a. Mathematical structures exist independently of anyone’s mind. b. Reality=Mathematics postulates that every mathematical structure gives rise to a reality that conforms to the mathematics of that structure. c. Given that Reality=Mathematics, there must exist a multiverse of every possible mathematical structure (i.e., Tegmark’s level IV multiverse). d. As a result we will find ourselves existing within one of these mathematically structured universes and the explanation for “why this particular mathematical structure?” is that our Postal Code specifies also which mathematical structure we inhabit. In addition, it must be a mathematical structure stable enough to support life (due to the Anthropic Principle).If Tegmark’s Reality=Mathematics theory is correct, then he would have explained the first (and most difficult) conundrum; namely, the First-Origin of reality (which includes all level I, II and III multiverses).I have spent much of my review summarizing my understanding of Tegmark’s theories of reality. I would now like to offer a critique of these theories. This critique I term the “Ugly Math” critique.Tegmark seems to only consider BEAUTIFUL mathematical structures when discussing his level-IV multiverse. I am now going to examine the nature of mathematics more closely. Since Tegmark does not mention “UGLY Mathematics” in his level-IV multiverse, I am going to create a level-V multiverse; namely, a multiverse which contains universes brought into existence by the existence of UGLY mathematical structures.I argue here that mathematicians tend to concentrate on just the beautiful mathematical structures and avoid the ugly ones. By “beautiful” I mean mathematical structures that are: concise, self-consistent, symmetrical, have broad scope or generality, are useful, appear to be true, and so on. In contrast, ugly mathematical structures lack one or more of these elements of beauty.Consider the function of addition (+). This function consists of an infinite mapping of pairs of numbers into a corresponding single number. For example, the function + includes the following 3 mappings: (2, 3) –> 5 (-4, 33) –> 29 (3.2, 1.1) –> 4.3+ is a very beautiful and useful mathematical structure and appears in every elementary math text book. However, let us consider some ugly variants of +. Consider the function +ugly1,1. I define this function to be: +ugly1,1: same as + for every pair of numbers except, if you attempt to add 7 and 19, you get -3.So +ugly1 is just like + except that it behaves differently on one particular number pair. This single exception makes it a different function.I am sure that most mathematicians never consider such a function. They don’t consider +ugly1,1 because it lacks the conciseness of +; it lacks the consistency of +; it lacks the generality of +, and so on. However, I must emphasize: +ugly1,1 is just as much a mathematical structure as is +!How many ugly variants of the function + are there? Well there exists only one + function but there are an infinite number of ugly variants! For example, I can define +ugly1,2 as follows:+ugly1,2: same as +ugly1,1 except if you try to add (12300.3 + 21.5) you get 12021So this function has two pairs (among an infinite number of pairs) that deviate from +.Clearly, there exist an enormous number of +ugly functions. They can deviate from + in terms of the value that a given pair will map to and they can also deviate from + in terms of the number of pairs that happen to be exceptional. For every beautiful mathematical structure there will exist a countless number of ugly variants and all of these ugly variants are just as mathematical as the beautiful ones!Concentration on beauty occurs in many areas outside of mathematics. For example, visual artists tend to focus on images that are beautiful. However, the vast majority of images are ugly — they look like noise on an analog TV late at night. The beautiful images (e.g., the Mona Lisa, a cartoon sketch, a photograph of a child, a minimalist, impressionist or surrealist painting, etc.) constitute only a tiny, tiny fraction of the abstract image space, which consists overwhelmingly of noisy, blurry, dirty, fuzzy, mushy, unrecognizable images.Likewise, mathematicians tend to concentrate so much on beautiful mathematical structures that they forget that the vast majority of abstract mathematical structures are exceedingly ugly (incoherent, non-generalizable, untrue, useless, non-concise, etc.). For every beautiful structure (appearing in some mathematical textbook or theoretical physics book) I can generate an INFINITE number of ugly mathematical structures. These ugly structures far, far, far outnumber the beautiful ones.If the theory of Reality=Mathematics is true, then the number of ugly universes that exist (created within my level-V multiverse) far outnumber all the other universes existing within Tegmark’s level-IV multiverse. If every beautiful mathematical structure gives rise to some universe, then so also must every ugly mathematical structure.Could a physical reality actually exist this is governed by an ugly mathematical structure? Consider an ugly variant of the + function. We could imagine a universe in which, every time creatures within that universe add two very large numbers A and B, they do not get (A+B); instead they get, say, ((A+B)-1). They are left with one less than what they started with. There are two possibilities in this case: (a) Maybe a missing element has been transformed into something that they cannot currently measure, or (b) maybe their reality is such that, when they have enough of something, they simply get one less when they try to combine them.I claim that my Reality=UglyMath theory (with its level-V multiverse) is scientific because (like Tegmark’s level-IV multiverse) it is also potentially testable and falsifiable.If a level IV multiverse exists (i.e. Reality=Mathematics) then a level-V multiverse must also exist (i.e. an infinite sea of ugly-math realities) because UglyMath is just as mathematical as is beautiful math. It is overwhelmingly more likely that we live in an ugly-math reality than in a beautiful-math reality. However, the Anthropic Principle states that our reality must be beautiful (consistent, stable) enough so that our universe enabled human life to develop. However, since the ugly-math realities are so much more common, we must conclude also that our universe, wherever possible, will consist of ugly-mathematical structures (but not so ugly as to preclude what we already observe in our universe).This is a testable (and therefore falsifiable) prediction. Thus, my theory of a level-V multiverse is a scientific (as opposed to religious or metaphysical) theory.I am not a physicist, but where I would look first (in an attempt to falsify my Reality=UglyMath theory) is in the area of dark energy and the accelerating expansion of the universe. I would look there because that is an area in which our universe could exhibit ugliness without that ugliness having caused our universe to be too unstable to support the development of life. Since ugly mathematical structures will be much more common that beautiful ones, they should dominate any reality. I predict that the pattern of dark energy acceleration should have fluctuated a lot over time (speeding up, then slowing down, then speeding up). This “ugliness” should be more likely if Tegmark’s Reality=Mathematics is true and if ALL mathematics structures are considered (not just the beautiful ones). If, however, the acceleration of the expansion of the universe is non-fluctuating, then it is much more likely that my hypothesis, and thus Tegmark’s hypothesis also, are both false.Notice that Tegmark uses the systematicity and stability of our universe as evidence FOR his hypothesis, because he is just considering just mathematically beautiful structures. I view this same systematicity and stability to be evidence AGAINST Tegmark’s hypothesis because ugly mathematical structures should always dominate over beautiful ones. If it is the case that mathematics brings about reality, then reality should overwhelmingly tend toward ugliness in its laws (except for where it would violate the Anthropic principle).I would like to conclude with some additional comments: concerning (a) the effect that Tegmark’s Postal Code might have on scientific methodology and (b) the relationship of mathematics to thought and thought’s relation to reality.Regarding methodology: Currently, when a scientist encounters some fundamental feature of reality, the scientist attempts to explain it by postulating a theory in which the observed feature is a necessary result of the theory. In the Postal Code approach, however, fundamental features of reality could, instead, always be explained away (by claiming that there exists, somewhere else, an alternative reality with that feature). This approach could result in a failure to create new theories that might actually explain (as opposed to explain away) some fundamental feature of our reality.Regarding thought and reality: I do not believe (as Tegmark seems to) that mathematical structures exist separate from our minds. I view the space of all mathematical structures as a subspace in a larger, space of thoughts. Thoughts are representational structures that intelligent minds encode and manipulate in order to survive within their environments. Some of those thoughts are mathematical; however, others (e.g. involving human actions, relationships, political plans, emotions, desires, etc.) are not mathematical.For example, the symbolic structure:Believes(Agent(John), Gave(Agent (Fred), Recipient(Mary), Object(Ring),Loc(LincolnMemorial), Time(2/21/2014)),Time(2/22/2014))is not itself about mathematical objects. It represents the fact that, on Feb. 22, 2014, John believes that Fred gave Mary a ring the day before at the Lincoln Memorial.The fact that this structure exists in someone’s mind (encoded, say, as neuronal firing patterns) or exists inside some artificially intelligent robot (encoded, say, as a symbolic structure) does not force us to conclude that this Believes structure is actually true. It should be clear to everyone that, while there is an enormous space of possible thoughts (including paranoid, delusional and nonsensical thoughts), only a tiny portion of these thoughts will accurately describe some aspect of reality.I maintain that all mathematical structures are a subset of all possible thoughts. Thus, the existence of mathematical structures (in human minds or in intelligence computers or in intelligent alien minds) does not imply that they have an objective existence apart from those minds.If minds have conceptual structures that correspond accurately with reality, then those structures will enable those minds to better survive within that reality. For example, if a vehicle is coming at you at high speed and you fail to manipulate internal conceptual representations (about the fact that the vehicle exists and its predicted trajectory) then you will fail to decide to jump out of the vehicle’s way and you won’t be around to continue having thoughts.Mathematical structures are also thoughts and thus exist ONLY within minds. It is a mistake to conclude that mathematical thoughts are independent of minds just because some of them happen to maintain a very good correspondence with a wide range of different aspects of reality.When I teach natural language processing (in a graduate-level course at UCLA titled “Language & Thought”) I tell my students that, although I might loosely state: “A written word W1 has meaning M1.”What I ACTUALLY mean is: “No written word ‘has’ a meaning. A written word is just scratches on a piece of paper. Those scratches, when viewed by a human eye, trigger some concept in the mind of that viewer. Thus, meanings exist only in minds, not on pages.”When we see the word “eats” that word triggers, in our minds, thoughts concerning the act of eating; the consequences of eating, etc. The meaning of the word “eat” is not in the word itself, but rather in our minds. In cases where our thoughts do not correspond to reality, then we say that our thoughts are false. Communication among humans is possible only because there is enough overlap in the conceptual structures that get triggered in different minds when different humans encounter the same sequences of words.People do not normally conclude that, since a given concept can be conceivably thought, there must exist some reality in which that concept is true. Likewise, mathematical thoughts, no matter how beautiful, only exist within minds. When someone places mathematical symbols on a piece of paper, they are just scratches. There is no meaning in them; rather they trigger meanings in appropriately prepared minds. When the eye of a mathematician (with appropriate background knowledge, etc.) sees those scratches, they trigger mathematical thoughts in that mathematician’s mind.I could have postulated a level-VI multiverse, consisting of an infinite sea of all possible thoughts. I could have then claimed that all such thoughts create their own alternative realities and thus claimed that Reality=Thought.This level-VI multiverse would contain thoughts both about mathematical structures and also about non-mathematical relations, such as, Eats(Agent(John), Object(steak)). But notice that if I were to postulate this level-VI multiverse, I would have to also include in it all weird and crazy thoughts, such as Eats(Agent(steak), Object(John)).I did not do this (perhaps missing out on a super grand idea). I did not do this because it seems to me that such a theory would be the ultimate form of solipsism and I prefer to believe that reality exists independent of our thoughts about reality.Let us return to my level-V ugly-math multiverse. A reason for not accepting a level-V multiverse is that it could (like Tegmark’s level-IV multiverse) also have a negative effect on scientific methodology. Currently, when deviations from a given theory are found in scientific measurements, scientists first check to make sure that their instruments are properly calibrated. In contrast, if they were to accept the premise that Reality=UglyMath, then they would tend to look for ugly theories to explain those deviations. For example, if a planet did not follow a perfect, elliptical orbit then, instead of first looking for an unseen body influencing that orbit, scientists might simply replace the elliptical formula with an ugly elliptical formula (one containing exceptions in the formula that occur exactly where the deviations in measurements were observed).Tegmark’s book is very insightful, thought-provoking and enjoyable to read; so I do highly recommend it. As he himself has said, he may be wrong (and I have attempted to shown him wrong, by extending his theory, along with making a falsifiable prediction concerning that extension).I do not have a solution to the two conundrums that Tegmark attempts to solve: (a) First-Origin — why anything at all exists and (b) Uniqueness — why our reality is the particular way it is. As to the uniqueness problem, I think that level I, II and III multiverses are a possibility but, given Ockham’s Razor, physicists should first consider theories with fewer (or perhaps no) infinities in them. Scientists should accept multiverses only when they are absolutely forced to; that is, when no finite alternatives exist. Perhaps that time has actually arrived in physics and the Postal Code approach is the only viable approach.In any case, let us not confuse thoughts (embedded within minds and referring to aspects of reality) with reality itself.Tegmark’s book has failed to convince me that mathematical structures cause our reality to come into existence (let alone bringing into existence an infinite number of alternative realities).

⭐In 1960, physicist Eugene Wigner wrote an essay titled “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences” in which he observed that “the enormous usefulness of mathematics in the natural sciences is something bordering on the mysterious and that there is no rational explanation for it”. Indeed, each time physics has expanded the horizon of its knowledge from the human scale, whether outward to the planets, stars, and galaxies; or inward to molecules, atoms, nucleons, and quarks it has been found that mathematical theories which precisely model these levels of structure can be found, and that these theories almost always predict new phenomena which are subsequently observed when experiments are performed to look for them. And yet it all seems very odd. The universe seems to obey laws written in the language of mathematics, but when we look at the universe we don’t see anything which itself looks like mathematics. The mystery then, as posed by Stephen Hawking, is “What is it that breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them to describe?”This book describes the author’s personal journey to answer these deep questions. Max Tegmark, born in Stockholm, is a professor of physics at MIT who, by his own description, leads a double life. He has been a pioneer in developing techniques to tease out data about the early structure of the universe from maps of the cosmic background radiation obtained by satellite and balloon experiments and, in doing so, has been an important contributor to the emergence of precision cosmology: providing precise information on the age of the universe, its composition, and the seeding of large scale structure. This he calls his Dr. Jekyll work, and it is described in detail in the first part of the book. In the balance, his Mr. Hyde persona asserts itself and he delves deeply into the ultimate structure of reality.He argues that just as science has in the past shown our universe to be far larger and more complicated than previously imagined, our contemporary theories suggest that everything we observe is part of an enormously greater four-level hierarchy of multiverses, arranged as follows.The level I multiverse consists of all the regions of space outside our cosmic horizon from which light has not yet had time to reach us. If, as precision cosmology suggests, the universe is, if not infinite, so close as to be enormously larger than what we can observe, there will be a multitude of volumes of space as large as the one we can observe in which the laws of physics will be identical but the randomly specified initial conditions will vary. Because there is a finite number of possible quantum states within each observable radius and the number of such regions is likely to be much larger, there will be a multitude of observers just like you, and even more which will differ in various ways. This sounds completely crazy, but it is a straightforward prediction from our understanding of the Big Bang and the measurements of precision cosmology.The level II multiverse follows directly from the theory of eternal inflation, which explains many otherwise mysterious aspects of the universe, such as why its curvature is so close to flat, why the cosmic background radiation has such a uniform temperature over the entire sky, and why the constants of physics appear to be exquisitely fine-tuned to permit the development of complex structures including life. Eternal (or chaotic) inflation argues that our level I multiverse (of which everything we can observe is a tiny bit) is a single “bubble” which nucleated when a pre-existing “false vacuum” phase decayed to a lower energy state. It is this decay which ultimately set off the enormous expansion after the Big Bang and provided the energy to create all of the content of the universe. But eternal inflation seems to require that there be an infinite series of bubbles created, all causally disconnected from one another. Because the process which causes a bubble to begin to inflate is affected by quantum fluctuations, although the fundamental physical laws in all of the bubbles will be the same, the initial conditions, including physical constants, will vary from bubble to bubble. Some bubbles will almost immediately recollapse into a black hole, others will expand so rapidly stars and galaxies never form, and in still others primordial nucleosynthesis may result in a universe filled only with helium. We find ourselves in a bubble which is hospitable to our form of life because we can only exist in such a bubble.The level III multiverse is implied by the unitary evolution of the wave function in quantum mechanics and the multiple worlds interpretation which replaces collapse of the wave function with continually splitting universes in which every possible outcome occurs. In this view of quantum mechanics there is no randomness—the evolution of the wave function is completely deterministic. The results of our experiments appear to contain randomness because in the level III multiverse there are copies of each of us which experience every possible outcome of the experiment and we don’t know which copy we are. In the author’s words, “…causal physics will produce the illusion of randomness from your subjective viewpoint in any circumstance where you’re being cloned. … So how does it feel when you get cloned? It feels random! And every time something fundamentally random appears to happen to you, which couldn’t have been predicted even in principle, it’s a sign that you’ve been cloned.”In the level IV multiverse, not only do the initial conditions, physical constants, and the results of measuring an evolving quantum wave function vary, but the fundamental equations—the mathematical structure—of physics differ. There might be a different number of spatial dimensions, or two or more time dimensions, for example. The author argues that the ultimate ensemble theory is to assume that every mathematical structure exists as a physical structure in the level IV multiverse (perhaps with some constraints: for example, only computable structures may have physical representations). Most of these structures would not permit the existence of observers like ourselves, but once again we shouldn’t be surprised to find ourselves living in a structure which allows us to exist. Thus, finally, the reason mathematics is so unreasonably effective in describing the laws of physics is just that mathematics and the laws of physics are one and the same thing. Any observer, regardless of how bizarre the universe it inhabits, will discover mathematical laws underlying the phenomena within that universe and conclude they make perfect sense.Tegmark contends that when we try to discover the mathematical structure of the laws of physics, the outcome of quantum measurements, the physical constants which appear to be free parameters in our models, or the detailed properties of the visible part of our universe, we are simply trying to find our address in the respective levels of these multiverses. We will never find a reason from first principles for these things we measure: we observe what we do because that’s the way they are where we happen to find ourselves. Observers elsewhere will see other things.The principal opposition to multiverse arguments is that they are unscientific because they posit phenomena which are unobservable, perhaps even in principle, and hence cannot be falsified by experiment. Tegmark takes a different tack. He says that if you have a theory (for example, eternal inflation) which explains observations which otherwise do not make any sense and has made falsifiable predictions (the fine-scale structure of the cosmic background radiation) which have subsequently been confirmed by experiment, then if it predicts other inevitable consequences (the existence of a multitude of other Hubble volume universes outside our horizon and other bubbles with different physical constants) we should take these predictions seriously, even if we cannot think of any way at present to confirm them. Consider gravitational radiation: Einstein predicted it in 1916 as a consequence of general relativity. While general relativity has passed every experimental test in subsequent years, at the time of Einstein’s prediction almost nobody thought a gravitational wave could be detected, and yet the consistency of the theory, validated by other tests, persuaded almost all physicists that gravitational waves must exist. It was not until the 1980s that indirect evidence for this phenomenon was detected, and only in 2015 was a gravitational wave directly detected.There is a great deal more in this enlightening book. You will learn about the academic politics of doing highly speculative research, gaming the arXiv to get your paper listed as the first in the day’s publications, the nature of consciousness and perception and its complex relation to consensus and external reality, the measure problem as an unappreciated deep mystery of cosmology, whether humans are alone in our observable universe, the continuum versus an underlying discrete structure, and the ultimate fate of our observable part of the multiverses.

⭐Having recently read an introduction to the philosophy of Mathmatics, I wanted to follow up by hearing about someone who tackles head on, one of the ancient questions, why a field of abstraction such as numbers, works so incredibly well at explaining the real world. Why have mathmatical patters developed by a single person with his pen, later have independent applications in the real world?This is perhaps best expressed in the title of one of Eugene Wigner’s papers, ‘the unreasonable effectiveness of Mathmatics in the natural sciences’. Why do a few simple formulas explain the fundemental structures of the universe?Since as far back as Pythagoras, one proposal is that Mathmatics in the fundemental substance of the universe. This is a bold and controversial thesis. There are many that try to defend Mathmatical platonism, that in some sense the realm of Mathmatics really exists. However few go as far as Max Tegmark and postulate that the Universe simple is one elaborate mathmatical structure. Whilst hard to accept, I find this an interesting and exciting idea, which is worth exploring. It would certainly explain why our physical theories are so full of equations that are simple and work so well.This subject alone could be elaborated across many books, however this hardly scratches the surface of all the topics that the author takes on. He throws out opinions on space, time, multiple universes, consciousness, the end of time, the meaning of life, the possibility of reality being a computer generation. This is a whistle stop tour of all the mind bending physical and metaphysical subjects you can think of.Of course much of this is wild speculation, however I love to hear about the crazy big ideas and he might just be right about one of two things. Why should physicists stick to number crunching, they’re as informed as anyone and entitled to take on the big philosophical questions. However it’s up to the philosophers to check for inconsistentcies and perhaps breath a little more restraint into the picture. These questions will live on as long as humans are alive and it’s always exciting to hear another radical voice. This is well worth reading.

⭐I join the consensus reality that this is a well written account of a couple of decades of exploring the big questions facing Physics and Philosophy and of a personal journey developing a coherent explanation for what we observe.I particularly like the anecdotes, illustrations, tables, summaries (in bullet points) and general handholding. He’s what I call a generous author.Consequently while I started as a sceptic, I finished accepting and feeling I understood the logic of his ‘crazy’ hypothesis.Like other reviewers, I wasn’t so impressed by the more skimmable last chapter, which seemed far less well constructed and less grounded, with a lot of ‘I think’ opinions about our fragile position in the universe. He probably feels he’s earned the right to bend our ears a bit, and indeed I think he has.However I felt his strongest conclusion came in the previous chapter where he declares, “We’ve found ourselves inhabiting a reality far grander than our ancestors ever dreamed of, and this means that our future potential for life is much grander than we thought.”

⭐This is a book where the title put me off. Surely the universe is a physical object, which is described by mathematics — what does it mean to say “Our Mathematical Universe”?Eventually, I bought a copy and read it. The book is pitched at a level that anyone could understand with very little formal physics or maths knowledge, though you are expected to understand scientific notation of numbers. There are very few formulae. I found the book very readable.I am really glad that I ended up buying the book. The theory it presents is weird, but completely believable. Really, this is that unusual case of a popular science book that itself does real science and makes a significant contribution to what we know about the world.— spoiler alert —The first few chapters introduce you to some physics: quantum mechanics, cosmology, inflation theory. These are presented very clearly and also persuasively. There is enough physics behind the presentation of inflation to show how it works as a theory and why it is so good at predicting the current state of our universe. Most popular science books just present it as a fait accompli, which ends up making it look rather silly as a theory. Similarly, the presentation of quantum mechanics, and particularly the Many Worlds theory, is clear and persuasive.At this point, the book launches into Max Tegmark’s own theory, which is not at all widely accepted. His theory is that the universe is not merely approximately described by mathematics, but is a mathematical structure. Some authors think that the world that we see is a simulation run on some supercomputer, rather like the film ‘The Matrix’ except that even the characters in it are simulations.When you run a simulation on a computer, you do it to find out the result. Imagine you want to know the answer to some piece of arithmetic. You can type it into a computer to find the result. The simulations that physicists run are more complicated, but they are the same sort of thing. What if you don’t run the simulation? The answer is still the same — it is defined by the mathematical structure. The only difference is that you don’t know the result.Imagine my simulation represents the movement of stars in a galaxy. Once I have defined the maths of the simulation, that is enough to define the position of every star at every point in time. I may chose to run the simulation, which will tell me what those positions are, but even if I don’t run it the maths has still defined exactly what the positions are. It doesn’t make any difference to the maths whether I run it or not. It only affects my knowledge of the result.If my simulation represents every particle in the universe, including those that make up our brains, the situation is no different. I can run the simulation, which will tell me the thoughts in those brains, but it will not affect what those thoughts are. That is defined by the maths.If you were God, you could run a simulation of the universe on a supercomputer, or you could create some custom hardware made out of elementary particles or strings or something and run the simulation on that — you could even call it ‘The real world’. But it wouldn’t make any difference to the maths. Everything that happens in the simulation is already defined by the mathematical rules: every stellar motion; every thought that happens in any intelligent minds that appear within the simulation. So it is a pretty easy business being God — you don’t have to create anything apart from the rules. Everything from then on is simply defined. No simulation required.But why are the rules the ones we know from Physics classes? What makes them special? This is where Tegmark makes his astonishing leap. No set of rules is special. They all exist, so all mathematical structures (subject to some constraints such as being internally consistent) have their own universes. Our universe is one of very many.The only thing that exists is Mathematics. It’s a crazy theory, but I for one cannot think of an argument against it.

⭐The first part is an excellent summary of cosmology and quantum physics that’s the most readable and informative I’ve read to date.Or maybe that’s an effect of having read too many books in the same genre. Either way the author makes light work of issues other authors struggle with, and each chapter concludes with a helpful brief outline to ease the process. The second part of the book deals with more esoteric subject matters,which is more challenging for the lay reader and requires more abstract imaginative processing to comprehend. Overall I found the book is readable and I rarely counted the pages or became over taxed intellectually,which to me, is the sign of an excellent author.

⭐I fascinating tour of Tegmark’s physics and mathematics view of the ultimate nature of reality, which touches on some mind blowing concepts, such as: an infinite physical universe, where everything may occur, including infinite versions of yourself separated by unsurmountable distance; and quantum suicide where you may in fact experience immortality (but everyone else sees you die). This book is definitely worth reading through for all these existential challenges. On the downside, these are all thought experiments that are probably impossible to prove as right or wrong (how can you verify if two possibilities both happen, since you can only experience one?) and perhaps the mathematical basis for reality is actually rooted in a socially constructed mathematical basis for understanding reality. Also Tegmark doesn’t point us towards any practical outcomes of the theories described, apart from a final chapter on how unique and fragile we may be in the multiverse, and how we need to protect our future from existential threats (with the techie favourite AI enslaving us all as the favourite threat). I’d really like to have read some more predictions about where current experiments around gravity waves and Higgs bosons might lead.But nonetheless this is the most enjoyable popular science book I have read in some years, and kept me hooked till the last page. Highly recommended.

Keywords

Free Download Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality in PDF format
Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality PDF Free Download
Download Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality 2014 PDF Free
Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality 2014 PDF Free Download
Download Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality PDF
Free Download Ebook Our Mathematical Universe: My Quest for the Ultimate Nature of Reality

Previous articleThe Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family by Peter Byrne (PDF)
Next articleParting the Cosmic Veil 2006th Edition by Kenneth R. Lang (PDF)