Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class by Charles Murray (PDF)

2

 

Ebook Info

  • Published: 2020
  • Number of pages: 528 pages
  • Format: PDF
  • File Size: 10.43 MB
  • Authors: Charles Murray

Description

All people are equal but, as Human Diversity explores, all groups of people are not the same — a fascinating investigation of the genetics and neuroscience of human differences.The thesis of Human Diversity is that advances in genetics and neuroscience are overthrowing an intellectual orthodoxy that has ruled the social sciences for decades. The core of the orthodoxy consists of three dogmas:- Gender is a social construct.- Race is a social construct.- Class is a function of privilege. The problem is that all three dogmas are half-truths. They have stifled progress in understanding the rich texture that biology adds to our understanding of the social, political, and economic worlds we live in.It is not a story to be feared. “There are no monsters in the closet,” Murray writes, “no dread doors we must fear opening.” But it is a story that needs telling. Human Diversity does so without sensationalism, drawing on the most authoritative scientific findings, celebrating both our many differences and our common humanity.

User’s Reviews

Editorial Reviews: Review PRAISE FOR COMING APART:”I’ll be shocked if there’s another book this year as important as Charles Murray’s Coming Apart.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}David Brooks, The New York Times”Mr. Murray’s sobering portrait is of a nation where millions of people are losing touch with the founding virtues that have long lent American lives purpose, direction and happiness.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}Wall Street Journal”[An] incisive, alarming, and hugely frustrating book about the state of American society.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}Bloomberg Businessweek”‘Coming Apart brims with ideas about what ails America.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}Economist”[A] timely investigation into a worsening class divide no one can afford to ignore.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}Publisher’s Weekly”[Murray] argues for the need to focus on what has made the U.S. exceptional beyond its wealth and military power…religion, marriage, industriousness, and morality.”―p.p1 {margin: 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px 0.0px; text-align: center; font: 12.0px Arial}Booklist (Starred Review) About the Author Charles Murray is the W. H. Brady Scholar at the American Enterprise Institute. He came to national attention first in 1984 with Losing Ground and most recently in 2012 with Coming Apart. He lives with his wife in Burkittsville, Maryland.

Reviews from Amazon users which were colected at the time this book was published on the website:

⭐Social constructionism holds that race and gender are shaped more by social forces and less by biological facts than people commonly realize. Charles Murray believes that this view has become an unscientific “orthodoxy,” and he offers a biological perspective that he believes can dispel much of this fuzzy thinking. It turns out that Murray’s biological perspective also rests on a great deal of fuzziness, though frequently concealed. In fairness to Murray, the genomic and psychometric research he surveys is difficult and technical. Murray recognizes this and provides several lengthy sections explaining this research clearly so that non-specialists can understand it. His success in doing so is probably the strongest feature of this book. The rest of the book, however, is more problematic. The issues are complex, and Murray does not always present the whole picture. Many readers will assume that Murray’s representations are accurate. Few will directly access the sources he cites, and fewer still will know how to evaluate the methods and findings of these sources, or the conclusions that Murray draws from them. In what follows, therefore, I will detail some significant problems with Murray’s account. NOTE: Some of the following citations refer to sources cited by Murray (indicated with an asterisk); others refer to scientific sources that will not be found in Murray’s book. Full reference information for all these sources can be found on the “References” page of my website, which can be accessed from my Amazon reviewer’s page.To begin with, Murray consistently overstates the evidence for genetic influence and understates the evidence for environmental influence on human diversity. He devotes large sections of the book to the former, often mentioning the latter only in passing, or in endnotes, or not at all. For example, Murray makes no mention of the Flynn Effect, one of the clearest indications of environmental influence on cognition (Mackintosh, 2011); he cites several sources on the validity of twin studies (pp. 215-217) but ignores Joseph’s (2015) extensive critique of that literature; he stresses the limits of early childhood interventions but says little about the social forces that undermine them (Protzko, 2015); and in discussing stereotype threat he emphasizes publication bias, yet says nothing about such bias in the publication of brain imaging studies, where it appears to be rampant (see Jennings & Van Horn, 2012). Along similar lines, the genetic methods and technologies that Murray admires often have serious reliability issues (for example, see de Gruijter et al., 2011 and Szpak et al., 2019), yet little or no attention is given to rigorous research designs finding environmental effects (e.g., Koch, D’Mello & Sackett, 2015). These examples are not exhaustive and several more will be given below. But Murray’s general stance is worth noting here—as is the fact that he frequently tags biological and genetic studies with adjectives like “seminal,” and “highly regarded” (pp. 102, 438), while ignoring or dismissing research widely recognized as supporting social construction (e.g., *Lewontin, 1972).It should be kept in mind that nearly all the evidence that Murray cites to argue for genetic determination is correlational. Even the brain imaging studies he reviews typically show neural correlates whose causal relationships to developmental and environmental influences are complex, multi-directional, interactive, and largely unknown. Most college students understand that correlation does not prove causation; but they rarely grasp just how ubiquitous and persistent correlation/causation fallacies actually are. Even professional researchers commit these fallacies when they survey vast fields of interrelated variables and make conscious or unconscious assumptions about causation which they then import into interpretations of the data based on circular reasoning. Hereditarians like Murray are notorious for falling into these traps—and some, like Arthur Jensen, for diving into them. Such fallacies are particularly misleading when used to portray group differences as genetic, not only because they frequently scapegoat ethnic minorities and confuse the public, but also because they concern processes of such complexity (like the neural interactions described above) that inferences about genetic causation are essentially unfalsifiable—i.e., nothing can be decisively proven or disproven, so anything goes. At times, Murray tries to avoid these fallacies, but he nevertheless succumbs to them and their associated circular reasoning on a regular basis, as exemplified by (but not limited to): genetic interpretations of statistical heritability estimates (e.g., pp. 228-29); ignoring environmental population stratification (e.g., p. 189); and referring to the causal role and “biological reality” of the “g” factor (pp. 231, 427) (regarding the latter, see Horn & McArdle, 2007 and Sternberg, 2019; regarding the former two examples, see below). Murray does have some awareness of the correlation/causation problem, and in one section he attempts to minimize it by asserting that prediction alone, without knowing causation, is good enough for a science of genomics (pp. 285-92). There are two problems with this tactic: First, predictions based on gene studies are weak, and, despite Murray’s optimism, are not showing much progress in becoming stronger (Turkheimer, 2019). And second, Murray himself is not happy with mere prediction—he repeatedly envisions an advanced science of genomics comparable to physics. But Murray’s references to physics focus on the 19th century; he avoids 20th century physics with its discoveries of inherent limits like the Heisenberg Principle and chaotic processes. Biology may be encountering similar limits in the 21st century.Turning now to Murray’s specific claims, he begins by examining whether psychological differences between males and females might be biological. In Chapters 2-4, he surveys much evidence for male/female psychological differences, and in each chapter he gives additional evidence that the differences persist worldwide, which he interprets as support for biological causation. But the meanings of this evidence are not always clear. Since these data are correlational, male/female differences may simply reflect socialization. Even the international studies, which are supposed to show pan-cultural gender differences, are problematic in that they focus on nations rather than cultures. This means that far from reflecting underlying biological causation, gender role differences—especially the larger differences in developed nations—may reflect, in part or in whole, choices of people in various cultures within these nations (e.g., working class and/or rural areas within the U.S.) to socialize their children along traditional lines. To supplement such findings, therefore, Chapter 5 covers biological and brain scan findings, which Murray feels to be the strongest evidence for male/female differences. As noted above, the brain scan data are correlational and are probably also inflated by publication bias. They have the same problems as the data in the first four chapters. However, other findings reported in this chapter do seem to present evidence for actual biological causation. These include studies of individuals with hormonal abnormalities and studies of responses to hormone injections. While the former are “natural experiments” with confounding variables, the latter are true randomized controlled trials, suggesting that hormones have a causal role. These findings do not contradict the role of social construction in gender roles and behavior, but they do indicate complex interactions between biology and socialization, or to put it another way, between sex and gender.The next four chapters focus on race. Murray’s position here will strike some readers as peculiar. He begins by noting that the race concept contributed to the rise of colonialism and slavery (p. 129) and adds that the term “race” no longer has any legitimate scientific usage (p. 135). But a few pages later (p. 148), he asserts that human beings fall into genetic clusters that conveniently correspond to the racial categories currently used in the U.S. So we will be talking about races after all, only now we are calling them “ancestral populations.” This back-and-forth about race embodies Murray’s struggle with the internal contradictions of his own position. He wants to drop the word “race,” but not the category. Yet it is the category that is socially constructed and that invites the scientifically unproductive conflation of social and biological causation. In the past, racial categories served to preserve the subordinate status of specific groups whose members bore phenotypic markers like skin color—whereupon the responses of those members to their subordination (that is, their temperament, intellect, speech, etc.) were judged inferior and regarded as proof of the rightness of that subordination. Murray now hopes to redefine membership in those same groups, not by phenotypic but by genotypic markers—whereupon psychological measurements, bogusly interpreted as genetic (see below), will establish the same old circular justification. Meet the new conflation; same as the old one.This conflation becomes more clear as Murray explains how his ancestral population clusters were discovered. Researchers led by Noah Rosenberg (*Rosenberg, Pritchard, & Weber, 2002) using a computer program called Structure found that the genomes of people whose ancestors came from each geographical continent are slightly more similar to each other than they are to those whose ancestors came from different continents. This is not surprising since genetic variants (alleles) change frequencies over time as populations disperse through migration, and these populations can therefore be expected to show greater similarity to neighboring populations and less similarity to more distant ones. But to Murray and others looking for a scientific basis for race, these clusters of genetic similarity hold great significance since they roughly align with the five major geographical continents (Africa, Europe, Asia, the Americas, and Oceania) and the racial associations of these continents for most Americans.But there are problems with this interpretation. First, the Structure program presupposes that the data will form clusters and that the number of such clusters will be whatever the researcher tells it to find. There are different techniques for deciding if a particular input number identifies objectively real clusters—but these techniques are complex, often vary with sampling, and do not always agree with each other. Therefore, most researches, including Rosenberg, publish multiple outputs, with different numbers of clusters, so that people reading the results can make their own judgments. Murray is not too troubled by this, as he states that this format “usually makes it easy” to see which results are “substantive” and which are not (p. 149). The potential for circular reasoning here is obvious, especially for someone like Murray who is motivated to see evidence for races. Another problem is that several studies have found that the Structure program tends to underestimate the number of ancestral population clusters (see Wang, 2017). In fact, Murray cites a later study (*Li, 2008) that found two additional clusters (which he interprets as roughly supporting the five-cluster theory), but he says nothing about several more recent and extensive studies that found still larger numbers of ancestral clusters, including Tishkoff, et al. (2009) (14 clusters), Shriner et al. (2014) (19 clusters), and Baker et al. (2017) (21 clusters). Overall, therefore, the human ancestral structure appears to be much more complex and multi-leveled than Murray portrays it, and not particularly supportive of the continental race theory.Another problem for Murray is that race categories only weakly differentiate people genetically. This was first discovered by *Lewontin (1972), who found that only about 6% of genetic variance in humans is associated with traditionally defined racial categories (Murray’s wording on p. 130 misleadingly implies that the number was close to 15%). This research has been replicated several different ways, with findings averaging around 4-10% (e.g., Feldman & Lewontin, 2008). Moreover, the interpretation of even this small portion of variance as support for racial clusters is questionable, given what was said above about migration and changes in allele frequency. In fact, geographical distance alone accounts for a far greater proportion of human genetic variance—over 75%. And when such distance is taken into account, the contribution of cluster variance drops to only about 2% (Handley, 2007)—and much of this 2% appears to be due to geographical barriers like oceans and deserts impeding migration and gene flow (*Rosenberg et al., 2005, p. 668). For such reasons, Rosenberg, like most other researchers, rejects a racial interpretation of continental clusters (*2005, pp.668-69).Murray knows this, and he has already, in effect, preemptively admitted it at the beginning of his “race” section—where he acknowledges that cluster differences are “minor,” and even adds that there are “many ways in which race is a social construct” (p. 157). But Murray is determined to keep this construct alive, and to do so he must show that race is intrinsically biological. So Chapter 8 considers evidence that selective pressures recently operated on the human population. I have already noted the unreliability of this data (see de Gruijter et al., 2011 and Szpak et al., 2019), and even the researchers that Murray cites have acknowledged this (e.g. *Akey, 2009 and *Haasl & Payseur, 2016). I will only add that: (1) all of this evidence involves correlations among molecular elements; it has not been connected to any observable phenotypes, and because much of it involves noncoding DNA it may have no connection with them whatsoever; (2) while some phenotypes have been plausibly identified as recently selected (e.g., lactase persistence), these traits follow a clinal rather than a clustered pattern—that is, they change gradually, vary independently of each other, and do not distribute according to Murray’s continental races; and (3) these traits all involve physical adaptations rather than the cognitive adaptations (like intelligence) that are so central Murray’s larger argument—Murray’s sole piece of evidence for causally induced cognitive adaptation is Belyaev’s 1959 experiment breeding foxes (*Trut, 1999), a study which has been questioned on a number of grounds, including significant sampling bias (Lord et al., 2020).In Chapter 9, Murray presents additional data in tables and scatterplots. Little is new here, since these data, in effect, simply re-present the cluster argument from Chapter 7. The one new development is that Murray relates this data to genes that correlate with psychological traits like positive affect and cognitive abilities. Since this analysis involves correlations, it has all the limitations already mentioned, plus an additional problem that I have not yet elaborated: environmental population stratification. Population stratification occurs when differences among populations cause researchers to draw erroneous conclusions. Murray does talk about this at times, but he almost always focuses on genetic rather than environmental confounds. Environmental population stratification arises from the fact that the environments of various genetically distinct populations are nonrandomly distributed—that is, people from different ancestral populations grow up in environments that almost always differ systematically from each other. This, in turn, means that correlations between biological genotypes and observed phenotypes are confounded by environmental factors, sometimes dramatically so, especially in the case of psychological traits, which are particularly susceptible to cultural influences. These environmental confounds cannot be factored out unless you know ahead of time exactly what each one is and how to test for it, which is essentially impossible (some writers, including Murray, hold that these influences can be statistically controlled, but this, once again, involves additional circular assumptions). All of this poses a serious problem that will haunt Murray’s analyses for the rest of his book—for example, in the “continental differences” that he surveys at the end of this chapter, and in his later advocacy of polygenic scores (pp. 280-283).Murray’s final substantive section (Chapters 10-13) allegedly deals with social class, but it would be more accurate to say that his argument here is that intelligence (measured as IQ) is the main source of success, that it is primarily genetically determined, and that social factors like poverty and race play only a minor role. This is the same argument Murray made in The Bell Curve (*Herrnstein & Murray, 1994). It was subjected to a number of devastating critiques (e.g. Kamin, 1995; Heckman, 1995), so I will not reiterate them here. I will merely note that environmental population stratification and correlation/causation fallacies lie at the heart of much of Murray’s reasoning in these chapters, as they did in The Bell Curve. For example, IQ and measures of success are both phenotypes that correlate positively with each other and negatively with certain racial group memberships (genotypes). So the relationship between IQ and success can be highlighted and the ones between both of these phenotypes and race can be disregarded, and along with them, the substantial environmental factors that contribute to the way IQ and success are racially and economically distributed in the U.S.Chapters 10 and 11 detail the statistical technique used to support many of the above claims—the so-called ACE model. Like many hereditarians, Murray relies heavily on this model, which parses measurements from twins and other related individuals into components of genetic and environmental variance that can then be added together to explain behavior. Most notable here is that Murray says nothing about the serious errors that routinely result from ignoring the limitations of this model. In an extensive analysis of all the most rigorous studies using the ACE model in the previous 30 years, *Turkheimer & Waldron (2000) found that designs based on that model had consistently failed to detect large portions of environmental variance. They concluded (pp. 91-93; see also *Turkheimer, 2000) that the additive assumptions of the ACE model rendered it unable to detect the complex and nonlinear ways that environmental forces actually interact with genetic factors and with each other to produce human behavior. To Murray’s credit, he does acknowledge these and other similar findings. But—characteristically—he then misrepresents them as implying that environmental factors can be disregarded as mere “noise” that can be ignored (p. 260). As with so many of Murray’s summaries, the reader will not know what these critiques actually say unless he or she goes to the original sources.Overall, then, Murray’s argument, both in this section and throughout the book, can be described as a hereditarian polemic. It rests on skewed data, over-interpretations of favored sources, under-interpretations of critical ones, and subtle (or not-so-subtle) misrepresentations of research findings. The result is an impressive edifice of hereditarian ideology built on a conceptual foundation of sand.

⭐This is another top-notch book by Charles Murray, in which he reviews the current state of knowledge regarding the biology and genetics behind differences in sex, race, and class. Murray is neither a biologist nor a geneticist by training, yet his grasp of the subject is excellent. His IQ is obviously well to the right end of the bell curve. I found only one minor error in his science.* Murray compares the state of knowledge regarding sex, race, and class differences to archaeological digs in various states of progress. He describes the digs for both sex and class to be in fairly advanced stages, with many artifacts found and undergoing analysis. The archaeological dig on race is not so advanced, but initial analysis indicates there is more worth exploring. As Murray is well aware of his reputation, he attempts to minimize the implications of human genetic diversity by stating “there are no monsters in the closet, no dread doors we must fear opening.” It is hard to believe a man as intelligent as Charles Murray actually believes this. The current societal and social science orthodoxy is that all people are blank slates with precisely the same cognitive potentials at birth, and given the proper environment any person can achieve anything they want in life. I don’t think even the most zealous “blank-slater” actually believes this and would likely concede there are differences in genetic endowments between different individuals, but you darn-well better not believe there are average differences between different groups, especially different racial groups. In part I of the book, Murray first explores sex differences in personality and cognitive abilities, perhaps because this is the least controversial of the three; few people doubt such differences exist. In particular, men and women have different means on some fundamental spectra of personality, including the people vs. things dimension. On average, women tend to prefer jobs that engage with people, whereas men prefer jobs that engage with things (e.g. machines or computers). When James Damore pointed out this fact as a possible explanation for why Google had fewer female than male programmers, he was promptly fired. Differences between men and women in career choices have many contributing factors that have nothing to do with a difference in average intelligence between the sexes, as today there are as many women attending medical school as men, but medicine tends also to be a more people-oriented occupation. There is, however, greater male variance in intelligence. The bell curve for men is broader and flatter compared to women; consequently, you will find more men at both extremes of the curve, which explains why you find more men in very cognitively demanding fields such as math and physics. Part III deals with genetics of class differences and summarizes what has been known for some time, namely that genes play an overwhelming role in determination of societal class. The take home message is largely summarized in Fig. 1 of part III, which shows the decreasing role of shared environment and the increasing role of genetics on IQ as a person ages. By the age of 18, genetics accounts for 70-80% of IQ, whereas the shared environment is effectively zero. The remaining 20-30% comes from the non-shared environment, i.e. the experiences unique to individuals. These are environmental influences that are near impossible to understand and hence, near impossible to favorably manipulate. The non-shared environment explains why genetics still only accounts for ~80% of the variance in IQ between identical twins raised in the same household. Similarly strong genetic influences and similarly weak (shared) environmental influences account for a number of different personality traits, as shown in Robert Plomin’s recent book Blueprint: how DNA makes us who we are. Nevertheless, Murray tries to assure his concerned readers that the strong role of genetics is no need for concern. He states: “Suppose it is found that the relationship of polygenic scores to phenotypic IQ scores in adolescence is about the same regardless of the childhood environment. I realize that many people dread such an outcome. In fact, that too will provide an incentive: to redirect our attention to fostering human flourishing for people with a wide range of ineradicable inequalities in gifts — a topic I take up in the concluding chapter.” Unfortunately, he makes no mention of the fact that the nature of a society is defined by the characteristics of the population that compose the society, including the average IQ of that population. For more on this, read: IQ and Global Inequality by Richard Lynn and Tatu Vanhanen. Currently, the average IQs of many Western nations are in decline due both to the higher fertility of their low IQ segments and mass immigration from low IQ countries. This bodes poorly for the future of the West and is most certainly a cause for concern. Part II on the genetics of race differences was interesting but disappointing, and the only reason I gave the book four stars, rather than five. Murray was too circumspect in this section and conceded too much to defenders of the current orthodoxy. For example, he discards the word race in favor of “ancestral populations.” He claims this was for legitimate scientific, not political, reasons, but makes a weak case to justify it. In the end, this concession makes little difference, since the terms mean essentially the same thing, at least from a scientific perspective. Part II contains little commentary about the underlying genetic/biological differences between races, only that such differences exist, and the taboo subject of race differences in intelligence is all but ignored. He tries to placate fearful readers with the following statement: “We already know of a genetically-grounded population difference on a highly sensitive trait that is far, far larger than any ancestral population difference we are going to find. The populations in question are males and females. The highly sensitive trait is the commission of physical violence against other humans. The undoubted genetic source of the difference is the Y chromosome. How big is the difference? Judge it by this: About 90 percent of all homicides are committed by males. If we can live with a population difference that huge on such an important behavioral trait, we can easily live with the smaller differences in continental populations that are likely to be found.” Given that Herrnstein and Murray wrote a section on the association of IQ and criminality in The Belle Curve, it is a little hard to believe he is not aware of race differences in criminal behavior, in particular how blacks are wildly over-represented in violent crime. Nationwide, blacks are approximately eight times more likely to commit murder than non-blacks. In New York City, blacks are about 31 times more likely, and Hispanics 12 times more likely, to commit murder than whites. Similar disparities are found in the city of Chicago. These racial disparities are considerably greater than the disparity between men and women, and they are just as likely to be genetic in origin. At least Murray finishes part II with an insightful observation known only to the few well-informed: “Part II has described a parallel universe. In the universe inhabited by the elite media and orthodox academia, it has been settled for decades that race is a social construct. In that universe, the lessons taught by Richard Lewontin and Stephen Jay Gould back in the 1970s and early 1980s still apply. In the universe inhabited by geneticists who study human populations, the 1990s saw glimpses of a new perspective, and the new century opens up fascinating stories that had previously been closed.” The Orwellian nature of the regime under which we live today is most starkly indicated by the acknowledgments section of the book. In order to write this book, Murray had to consult with many experts in genetics and other fields of science. However, in order to get their feedback, he had to assure them that he would not mention their names. Presumably, many, if not most, of the experts he consulted were tenured professors who can safely speak the truth without fear of summary termination from their jobs. While their jobs may be secure, they still remain vulnerable to exposure and slander by the legacy media and social ostracism by their professional colleagues. For proof of this, one need look no further than James Watson. Such zealous suppression of dissenting viewpoints and inconvenient facts indicates that the subject of race has moved beyond mere political orthodoxy and into the realm of religion. It is also an indication of just how weak is the 100% environmental explanation for human diversity. Since the ruling regime cannot refute the facts, its only option is to suppress them.*In his description of X-chromosome inactivation, he stated that both X chromosomes remain active in 12-20% of cells in women, but it’s actually 12-20% of genes on the otherwise inactive X that continue to be expressed in most cells of a woman’s body.

⭐Murray has written a very valuable, concise book on the most exciting developments in human sociobiology. Most impressively, he has done so in a way that 1) uses several statistical concepts and 2) is readable for a non-STEM/stats graduate like myself. Despite the numerous media calumnies that make him out to be a Nazi, Murray writes in a very empathetic and positive manner. Women, non-whites, and working-class people are not talked down to or demeaned. His chapters on gender differences especially highlight the absurdity of claiming any group to be innately better than another.Murray has put together the evidence suggesting biological/genetic explanations for certain differences between genders, races, and classes. The first and third have the most comprehensive/consistent evidence behind them, while the second is more rooted in speculation. But even on race, the sequencing of human genomes has shown a great deal of genetic influence on non-behavioural traits. If the taboo weakens, as Murray predicts, we might one day find that some cognitive differences can also be detected with genomic research methods. I am personally skeptical of this- if anything, the consensus that Race Is A Social Construct has gotten more entrenched in the past few years.However, the Race/IQ topic is small beans in this book. The book’s gender chapters are perhaps the most engrossing, and I suspect a casual liberal will find much to agree with. Murray points out how sex differences in personality and work/study preferences actually become *larger* in more gender egalitarian countries. Therefore, Western European countries have more “stereotypical” gender divides in college majors than poorer nations elsewhere. Murray of course notes that female representation in once all-male fields did improve dramatically after the first two waves of feminism in the 19th-20th centuries. However, since then progress has seemed to stagnate. It is convincingly shown that women’s choices, based in large part on biological inheritances, are driving this, not Western male sexism.Similarly, Murray points out that the role of genetic factors in class differences can be low when public goods are unevenly distributed. He notes that one study found heritability rising in sync with the expansion of public education. But there is a point of diminishing returns. Once a country has reached a certain stage of development, anything beyond ‘normal’ parenting and schooling is rarely effective. The scientific literature on growth mindsets, stereotype threats, and early childhood education are all rather weak. Most often, big pedagogical schemes have no impact in the long run.Human Diversity has so many citations that the final 30% of its pages are exclusively taken up by them. But the book is all the better for it. Studies from geneticists, sociologists, and neuroscientists are all listed. Murray places the empirical literature in the hands of the reader, so that they can see the science is fairly well settled. And it is not settled in the direction that modern progressivism has us believe. In our inequality-obsessed age, where war cries for ending all inequities are the norm, this book is needed now more than ever.

⭐Will not be liked by lefties or wokes.

⭐As a teacher I am always fascinated by gender differences and this book proves what I have always believed: there are profound genetic differences between the sexes. It’s not fashionable to admit this, but the shibboleth of gender similarity needs to be destroyed. The book isn’t an easy read but it’s definitely an interesting one.

⭐A treasure trove of readable and interesting information relevant to Murray’s topics. Murray says that he presents only those points which he is prepared to defend against politically motivated criticism, but that still leaves him a huge amount. My takeaways are that any functioning society has to deal with diverse personalities, because the greatest divide is between men and women, and that no scaleable intervention to modify personality to make the people suit their government better has yet been found. By the way – don’t miss the Appendix on male variability, the last matter before the notes start.

⭐Murray has written a very readable introduction to the current state of knowledge regarding biological differences between the sexes, races and classes. He quite conclusively knocks out the foundations of the orthodox liberal position that almost all such differences are social constructs.There is a vast trove of material here, far more than can be absorbed in a single reading. I plan on rereading the whole book slowly spending more time on each chapter and digging more deeply into the statistics.I find it amazing and sad that this book has essentially been ignored by the mainstream media. If the arguments in this book hold up, and there seems no reason to suspect they won’t, they explain the background to most of the pressing social issues of the day. Without this background it is hard to see how we can find any effective solutions.I recommend this book unhesitatingly to anyone who both has an open mind and a concern for the health of our communities.There is a long somewhat polemical review below that purports to demolish Murray’s arguments, however the review ignores Murray’s attempts to deal with these arguments. One very basic point, the review suggests that Murray ignores the role of socialisation in male/female differences. Murray actually spends a lot of time reviewing the evidence that male/female differences are more pronounced in more egalitarian societies like modern Scandinavia than Arab countries. This is a key piece of evidence that has to be explained by the “it’s all a social construct “ folks.

Keywords

Free Download Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class in PDF format
Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class PDF Free Download
Download Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class 2020 PDF Free
Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class 2020 PDF Free Download
Download Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class PDF
Free Download Ebook Human Diversity: The Biology of Gender, Race, and Class

Previous articleFamilies, Schools, and Delinquency Prevention by Glenn C. Loury (PDF)
Next articleIn Pursuit of Happiness and Good Government by Charles Murray (PDF)